In order to define species as
individuals, Sober takes the first step to argue that breeding populations are
“biological individuals”. By this he means, breeding populations, “a set of
local demes linked to each other by reproductive ties but not so linked to
demes outside the set” (156), can be defined as individuals.
Sober writes that the key of
individuality is “causality” (153), instead of similarity. In order to define
an individual, we have to consider the existence of synchronic and diachronic
interrelations. Synchronic interrelation means that the units in the individual
group should have causal interrelations during the same period of time, such as
when the cells in your body cooperate together. Diachronic interrelation means
that during different periods of time, different units should be linked
together by the “casual processes of ontogeny” (154). The units should have a
kind of “ancestor/decent relationship” (156), such as when all the cells in
your body grow from the very first embryo cell. Moreover, to define an
individual, we also have to distinguish when the individual ceases to exist,
which means the individual should have a precise “life-death
According to Sober, breeding
populations can be considered “individuals”, since the “earmarks” of
individuality can be applied to breeding populations (157). Breeding
populations have reproductive links within the group, which is a synchronic
interrelation. And they have ancestor/decent relationship because of the
reproductive links. This is the diachronic interrelation. Breeding populations
emerge when one breeding population buds off from a parent population, cease to
exist when all member in the population “die or fall to reproduce.” This meets
the requirement of life-death cycle.
I agree with Sober’s claim that
breeding populations are individuals. Sober’s definition of “biological
individuals” is fairly solid, and breeding populations do indeed fall into his
definition of “biological individuals.” However, there will be some
disagreement on this claim. I will discuss about these critics in following
passages. When defending Sober’s claim, I will pay attention to avoid the
discussion of “species” here, and focus on Sober’s definition of individuality.
If a breeding population
separates from the parent population at certain time, according to Sober’s
definition, we should say a new individual population emerges. But can we
rashly make this conclusion? For instance, if these two populations reintegrate
later, can we still be so confident about our previous judgment? The answer is
yes. The occurrence of reintegration does not affect the fact that two breeding
populations had existed as two individuals. The German reunification in 1990
did not deny the fact that, when West Germany and East Germany separated, they
had been existed as two independent countries. The property of individuality is
based on the time period we observe the breeding population.
Other possible critics may argue
that the extent of individuality is rather arbitrary. To what extent can a
group of breeding population be counted as an individual? For example, we
assume that all gorillas in one continent have the possibility to interbreed
with each other. If we define all gorillas on this continent as a single
individual, how can we define the smaller troops of gorilla? In fact Sober did
answer this question. He said that “whether a given collection counts as one
individual or as many will depend on the magnifying power of lens we use” (158).
When saying breeding populations are individuals, we do not deny the relation
between each population. As long as breeding populations meet Sober’s
definition of “biological individuals”, they can be grouped as bigger
“individuals”.
There are some controversies
when we divide populations into individual according to the criteria of
“interbreeding”. Consider this example: we assume that a group of gorilla is
genetically identical and breed from same group of ancestor, but they have
reproduction isolation. For instance, a portion of them would like to
interbreed one month later than others. In Sober’s view, breeding isolation
leads to the separation of two individuals. However, if these gorillas live
together, forage together, and even form into a same troop under the same adult
male leader, then they do have interrelation with each other, compared to the
other groups that have a geographic isolation. Why cannot we define them as a
single “biological individual”? In my opinion, these gorillas can be regarded as
one single group, but the breeding barrier violates Sober’s biological
consideration. Sober’s “biological individual” is based on the interrelations,
especially breeding relations, among the organisms. The gene flow is the key to
distinguish a single biological individual. In our gorilla example, even though
they still live in the group, the breeding barrier will finally lead to the
isolation in these gorillas’ social structure. The physical isolation will
appear when the male leader gorillas no longer regard those female gorillas. On
the longer time scale, these two groups may even develop physical breeding
isolation. In this sense, breeding isolation is critical when we consider a
group of organisms as “biological individuals.”
No comments:
Post a Comment